Skip to main content

PARI PASSU PRINCIPLE

This chapter delves into the nature of the pari passu principle, which supposedly requires all unsecured claims of an insolvent company to be met proportionately from the insolvent's estate. It argues that there is widespread misunderstanding about the role of this principle. The principle is claimed by commentators to be responsible for the orderliness of corporate liquidation, to explain and justify the collectivity of the liquidation regime and the rules providing for the avoidance (or more accurately, adjustment) of certain types of transaction, and to ensure fairness to all of the insolvent's creditors. The central claim in the chapter —that none of these functions can properly be attributed to the principle —is illustrated by empirical evidence of how the estates of insolvent companies are in fact distributed, the statutory provisions which help put the principle in its proper place, and the case law said to support it. The Authentic Consent Model is deployed to demonstrate that the pari passu rule —often called the ‘equality’ principle—has little to do with ‘real’ equality. The chapter shows what it claims is the actual role of ‘formal’ equality of the sort enshrined in the ‘equality’ principle.

Keywords:   pari passu principlecollectivitytransaction avoidancefairnessorderlinessnon-distribution principleliquidation regimecorporate liquidation

1. Introduction

This chapter analyses the pari passu principle of insolvency law, and asks how it relates to other principles available for the treatment of claims in corporate liquidation. The discussion in section 2, below, reveals that the principle has rather limited effect in governing distributions of the insolvent’s estate. Not only do various types of secured claim fall beyond its ambit, even unsecured claims are often exempt from its application. Nevertheless, the principle thrives both in judicial rhetoric and in academic arguments. For example, many a challenge to the different priorities accorded to different types of claim in a company’s insolvency begins with an incantation of the pari passu principle. Finch states (on the second page of her encyclopaedic study on secured credit):

The normal rule in a corporate insolvency is that all creditors are treated on an equal footing—pari passu—and share in insolvency assets pro rate according to their pre-insolvency entitlements or the sums they are owed. Security avoids the effects of pari passu distribution by creating rights that have priority over the claims of unsecured creditors.1

Bridge sees an inherent tension between the ‘two fundamental principles of credit and insolvency law’, that of the freedom of contract which allows one to (p.93) bargain for priority, and the mandatory pari passuprinciple.2 And Cranston, after considering and discounting lesser objections to the existence of secured credit, concludes that ‘there are other social policies antipathetical to extensive security, like the pari passuprinciple[,] which are less easily refuted.’3

The pari passu principle is said to be ‘the foremost principle in the law of insolvency around the world’.4Commentators claim to have found this principle entrenched in jurisdictions far removed from ours in geography and time.5 At English law, statute itself seems to confirm Finch’s ‘normal rule’, that all creditors of an insolvent company are to be treated ‘equally’ by having their pre-insolvency claims abated rate and rate alike.6 The principle is thought to be ‘all-pervasive’, and its effect is to ‘strike down all agreements which have as their object or result the unfair preference of a particular creditor by removal from the estate on winding up of an asset that would otherwise have been available for the general body of creditors.’7 The Cork Committee, despite noting significant exceptions to the principle, reiterated its fundamental importance.8 The principle is said to be supported both by the need for an orderly liquidation of insolvents’ estates, and by requirements of fairness. So it is not surprising that its invocation as the starting point for, say, the debate on the priority of secured or preferential claims, weights the argument in a particular way Since the pari passu principle has been recognized so widely and for so long as vital, and since it serves such desirable aims as orderliness in liquidation and fairness to all creditors, any deviation from it must be a cause for concern. It seems to follow therefore that:

Before a creditor is entitled to claim a preferred position it must be demonstrated that deviation from the inveterate and equitable pari passu principle is warranted.9

On this view, the priority (say) of secured or preferential claims is an abnormality, a pathology to be diagnosed and controlled, perhaps even ‘cured’. Since ‘equality’ is the norm, the onus must be on those supporting differing priorities to justify their claim.10 To the extent that their efforts are unpersuasive, the case for (p.94) priority must be considered not established, and the ‘default principle’ of ‘equality’ must prevail.11

This chapter seeks to overturn this order of things. It is argued here that the pari passu principle is rather less important than it is sometimes made out to be, and does not fulfil any of the functions often attributed to it. It does not constitute an accurate description of how the assets of insolvent companies are in fact distributed. It has no role to play in ensuring an orderly winding up of such companies. Nor does it underlie, explain, or justify distinctive features of the formal insolvency regime, notably, its collectivity. The case-law said to support the pari passu principle serves actually to undermine its importance. And the principle has nothing to do with fairness in liquidation. An important part of the argument here seeks to explain the actual role of the principle. If the arguments made here succeed, then the initial onus of justifying their position shifts from those arguing in favour of the priority of secured and preferential creditors, etc., to those who support a more ‘equal’ distribution of the insolvent’s estate. The chapter concludes by analysing the likely effect of the recent abolition of the preferential treatment previously accorded to certain tax claims.

Since there is confusion in the literature about the correct identification of the pari passu principle, it would be useful to begin with a word on terminology. The pari passu principle, as it appears in (corporate) insolvency law, has a fairly specific purpose. The standard statement of the principle seeks to be informative, to answer the broad question how insolvency law decides on the treatment of different types of creditor. The answer offered by the principle is that insolvency law ‘takes them exactly as it finds them.’12 Put differently, creditors holding formally similar claims under non-insolvency law are to be paid back the same proportion of their debt in their debtor's insolvency.13 The pari passu principle, then, is one manifestation of formal equality in insolvency law.

Objections of the principles.

However, it is not the only one. As explained in the following section, insolvency law itself enshrines various rejections of the pari passu principle, the most notable for our purposes being that in favour of preferential creditors. Some of the claims held by the insolvent’s employees, and some tax liabilities owed by the insolvent, rank ahead of general claims, such that all preferential debts must be discharged in (p.95) full before general unsecured creditors are paid anything.14 The factor which causes confusion is that preferential claims also abate rateably as amongst themselves. Some commentators have therefore been led to regard the treatment of preferential creditors inter se as another application of the same pari passu principle.15 But this view is unsound in several different ways. Most obviously, it ignores the received understanding of the nature of the ‘equality’ principle, that the determination of ‘equality’ is to be made by pre-insolvency law.16 Second, it reduces the principle to triviality, since the principle now provides simply that those determined by insolvency law to be equal are to be treated equally by insolvency law. But now pari passu is not a rule or a restriction or a standard. It neither imposes a requirement which insolvency law must fulfil, nor does it shape that law in any way. It is merely a description of what insolvency law actually does, and it fits perfectly with whatever scheme of priorities that law might devise. As a triviality the principle is harmless, but for the same reason it is also uninformative. It no longer says anything about why insolvency law chooses to declare certain creditors to be ‘equals’. Finally though, and confusingly, the commentators who regard the distribution to preferential creditors inter se to be governed by the pari passu principle, still accept that the existence of preferential claims itself constitutes an exception to that principle.17 Viewed thus, their position becomes something of a paradox: the treatment of preferred claims is both an exception to, and yet an application of the pari passu rules! It is difficult to imagine too many other situations which both exemplify and contradict one and the same principle.

It is suggested that this view of the ‘equality’ principle, which renders the principle both trivial and paradoxical, is unhelpful and should be abandoned. A little care with terminology dissolves the paradox and restores the principle to its roots. A distinction must be drawn between the sort of formal equality represented by pari passu(the equality of creditors as determined by the pre-insolvency form of their claim) and other manifestations of formal equality introduced by insolvency law itself (such as that which holds between certain employee-claims, but not between these and claims held by a trade creditor, say). Accordingly, references to pari passu in this chapter are to be understood in line with this distinction. To break the monotony of recurrence, ‘the “equality” rule (or principle, or norm) will sometimes be employed as synonymous with pari passu. Formal equality other than that enshrined in the pari passu principle will be clearly identified by the context.

(p.96) 2. The myth of pari passu distribution

Despite the hold exercised by the ‘equality’ principle on the imagination of most insolvency lawyers,18 the principle is sometimes acknowledged, as a descriptive matter, not to have too much application in the real world. After proclaiming that the principle is ‘fundamental and all-pervasive’, Goode adds that ‘This, at least, is the theory of insolvency law.’19 Fidelis Oditah, who also regards it as ‘fundamental’, explains at the same time that the pari passu norm is ‘shallow’, since it is subject to numerous exceptions, and since it does not in itself acknowledge the ‘obvious truth’ that insolvency law often exempts those holding certain dissimilar pre-insolvency rights from having to submit to an ‘equal’ distribution.20 The Cork Report noted that rateable distribution among creditors is rarely achieved.21 And Keay and Walton state that the ‘equality’ principle is 'nothing more, and has little relevance, other than to act as a convenient default principle.'22

It would be instructive to consider just how extensive these deviations from the ‘normal rule’ really are. Disregard for the moment the priority given to those with a consensual property right. Goode explains that the treatment of secured creditors, suppliers of goods under reservation of title (ROT) clauses, and ‘creditors for whom the [debtor] company holds assets on trust’, all are not to be considered true exceptions to the pari passuprinciple, since ‘such assets do not belong to the company and thus do not fall to be distributed among creditors on any basis.’23 Some five categories of true exceptions established by statute can still be identified.

The first category consists of the rights of insolvency set-off, which are wider in effect than those available outside insolvency. Set-off applies whenever there have been mutual credits, mutual debits or other mutual dealings, before the onset of liquidation, between the debtor and any of its creditors.24 The cross-claims need not impeach the debt owed to the insolvent, so long as the requirement of mutuality is satisfied.25 ‘The right of set-off on insolvency represents a major incursion into the pari passu principle’, since to the extent that there are mutual credits, (p.97) debits or other dealings, the creditor able to assert set-off rights gets a pro tantopriority over others.26 What is especially significant given our focus, this priority is mandated by the Legislature,27 and operates automatically at the date of the winding-up order without the need for any intervention by either party.28 Parties, in other words, are compelled to breach the pari passu principle.

A second category is constituted by pre-liquidation creditors who can compel payment by virtue of their ability to inflict certain types of harm on the insolvent estate. This category covers payments to avoid forfeiture of a lease, distress or termination of a contract.29 In general, creditors whose continued cooperation is desired by the liquidator may be able to extract payments in respect of pre-insolvency debts.30

Then there are preferential claims themselves. These include certain debts related to the insolvent’s employees. These include any sums in relation to occupational pension schemes, remuneration of employees up to £800, accrued holiday pay, and any sums loaned and used for the specific purpose of paying employees’ remuneration.31 Before the Enterprise Act 2002 came into force, preferential status was also accorded to various taxes collected by the debtor on behalf of the Crown, including some PAYE deductions, unpaid VAT, unpaid car tax, general betting, bingo, and gaming licence duties, some pool betting duties, and unpaid social security contributions. Levies on coal and steel production, beer duty, lottery duty, insurance premium tax, air passenger duty, and landfill tax had also been added to this list.32 These have now been abolished.33

Instead, the Enterprise Act has created a ‘special reserve fund’ (also referred to as the ‘prescribed part’ and the ‘ring-fenced sum’) for unsecured creditors (including the Crown in right of unpaid taxes).34 This fund consists of a particular proportion of the company’s net property, which includes the proceeds of realization of assets subject to a floating (though not a fixed) charge. The proportions are at present as follows. If the net property of the company undergoing formal insolvency proceedings is less than £10,000, then the prescribed part consists of 50 per cent of that property. Where the company's net property is at least £10,000, the prescribed part consists of 50 per cent of the first £10,000, plus (p.98) 20 per cent of the property exceeding this sum, provided that the value of the prescribed part shall not exceed £600,000.35 With respect to this fund, the claims of unsecured creditors rank ahead of any claims secured by a floating charge. It should be noted that the treatment of creditors eligible to make claims against the special reserve fund is not governed by the pari passu principle. As explained above, this principle requires the implementation within insolvency law of the priorities to be found in the general law.36 Under the general law, the holder of a crystallised floating charge would rank ahead of unsecured creditors with respect to the proceeds of sale of the property subject to this charge. This order is overturned with respect to the special reserve fund. It follows that the claims eligible to being vindicated against this fund constitute another exception to the pari passu principle.

Finally, various types of debt have been deferred by statute. These include debts owed by the insolvent to a director (including shadow director) found liable for wrongful or fraudulent trading, and ordered to be deferred by the court.37 Claims held by the debtors shareholders or other members qua members also fall under this head.38

Many commentators consider there to be another statutory exception to the ‘equality’ principle.39 Creditors whose claims arise after the winding-up order has been handed down are given a privileged position. Statute provides that their claims are to be treated as part of the expenses of liquidation, are therefore to be given ‘pre-preferential’ status (i.e. ranking ahead of preferential creditors), and are to be paid, not proved.40 In addition, utility suppliers ‘may make it a condition of the giving of the supply that the [liquidator] personally guarantees the payment of any charges in respect of the supply’.41 However, it is submitted this type of claim cannot properly be regarded as an exception to the pari passu principle, since, as explained above, that principle governs the treatment of those holding formally similar claims under pre-insolvency law. By definition, post-liquidation creditors do not, in that capacity, have any pre-liquidation claims, so pre-insolvency law simply has nothing to say about the nature or treatment of their claims. It follows that they do not fall within the ambit of the ‘equality’ principle.42

So the claims of creditors able to assert set-off, utility companies, pre-liquidation creditors with post-insolvency leverage, several different types of (p.99) preferential claims, claims of unsecured creditors against the special reserve fund, and claims of deferred creditors, all are exempt from the pari passu principle. And even these ‘deviations’ from the ‘normal rule’, while apparently substantial, might in fact be ‘something of a minor qualification’ to the ‘equality’ norm.43 There are numerous other types of creditor not affected by it. Under certain circumstances, this includes claims held by accountants, solicitors, stockbrokers, factors, and bankers, all of whom might be able to benefit from common law liens which arise by operation of law.44 Statute gives the unpaid seller a lien on the goods sold, and rights of stoppage in transit.45 If the insolvent was insured, a party injured by its actions (a tort creditor) is subrogated to its rights against the insurer.46 If the liability in question arose under circumstances governed by the Road Traffic Act 1988, the insurer might be liable to the tort creditor even in those circumstances where it would have been able to avoid or cancel the policy as against the insured.47 This of course continues to disregard those able to assert consensual property rights in some assets ostensibly within the insolvent’s estate.

Consider these principles in the light of data on the sources of external funding for small to medium sized enterprises (SMEs),48 which provide insolvency law with most of its business.49 In a survey covering the period 1995–1997, 47 per cent of this was found to have been provided by banks (who often take security), 27 per cent by hire purchase/leasing firms (proprietary rights), six per cent by partners and shareholders (may or may not be deferred by statute), six per cent by factoring businesses (liens and consensual proprietary rights), four per cent by other individuals, four per cent by other sources, three per cent by venture capitalists (equity claimants, hence ranking below debtors), and one per cent by trade customers (who have the option of setting up Kayfordtrusts50). Also important, especially for small businesses, is trade credit. By some estimates, stocks and flows of trade credit are twice the size of bank credit.51 At least some of the credit in this category also generally falls beyond the application of the ‘equality’ norm. One survey found that well over half the suppliers surveyed (59 per cent) used ROT (p.100) clauses.52 This figure seems to rise dramatically, the more troubled the debtor in question.53

 

These are of course the sources from which firms raise capital while they are solvent. These figures do not directly indicate the composition of the overall debt of firms which are in financial distress, or which are undergoing some formal insolvency procedure. Intuitively, however, it would be surprising if the debt outstanding when a firm became distressed generally had a structure very different from the one mentioned above. And in fact there are some fresh data which confirm this intuition. Julian Franks and Oren Sussman have recently compiled a data set of more than 500 firms which had bank debt, and which were in financial distress.54 This confirms that the structure of debt of the firms in the ‘rescue units’ of the three banks studied is very similar to that for solvent firms as a whole.55

Even more significant is the fact that, in an overwhelming majority of formal insolvency proceedings, nothingsdistributed to general unsecured creditors (the only category of claimant truly subject to the pari passu rule56). It is estimated that there are zero returns to them in 88 per cent of administrative receiverships, 75 per cent of creditors’ voluntary liquidations, and 78 per cent of compulsory liquidations. On average, they receive 7 per cent of what they are owed.57

So while the matter is an empirical one, and while the position would of course vary from debtor to insolvent debtor, the discussion so far and these statistics show that most types of claim either are or can be exempted from the application of the pari passu principle. It is also likely that in most liquidations, hardly any claimant is paid pari passu. Given these reasonable deductions, one might perhaps be (p.101) forgiven for questioning whether it is fair to describe the pari passu principle as ‘the normal rule in a corporate insolvency’.58 In fact, it is the differing priorities of claims which seem to represent the rule. What seems certain is that, in the distribution of the assets of insolvent estates, ‘equality’ between different types of claim must be very much the exception. As Dalhuisen has put it, ‘It is … the ranking… and not the equality, that is the essence of bankruptcy and of creditors [’] relationships more generally.’59 Put differently, even if unsecured claims other than preferential claims form the bulk of the claims in most liquidations, most of the available assets would not be distributed ‘equally’. The pari passu rule is supposed to govern distributions. It should be obvious, however, that distribution in accordance with this rule is virtually non-existent.60

Some readers would object that the discussion so far does little more than state the obvious, since everyone knows that the current law leaves little room for anything to be distributed pari passu in an overwhelming proportion of insolvencies. These readers dramatically underestimate the extent to which insolvency scholarship still clings to the pari passu myth. Leading insolvency scholars (and courts) regularly assert that this jurisdiction has a ‘pari passu insolvency regime’, that the ‘equality’ rule has been varied ‘only slightly [] in respect of personal claimants’, that the ‘present law [] is disinclined to force particular classes of creditors to shoulder greater burdens’ than others by causing derogations from the ‘equality’ principle in favour of the latter (or against the former).61 With respect, such assertions very mis-leadingly push the pari passu principle to the fore as currently the dominant method for the distribution of insolvent estates. They are then used as premises in further analysis which in turn is often (though not always) distorted as a result. That is to be regretted. Much of science could not progress till it had rejected the false geocentric picture of the cosmos. In its rather more modest sphere, insolvency scholarship must somehow tear itself away from the equally false view that the ‘equality’ principle occupies the centre of the insolvency law universe.62

(p.102) Still, let us take seriously the objection noted above. Perhaps the discussion so far has missed the point. The claim that priority is a pathology might not be a descriptive one after all. Those making it might, on reflection, be willing to concede that the pari passu principle reflects little of reality, which (they might come to accept) consists of widely divergent priorities accorded to different types of claim. The critics of differential priority might now argue that the ‘equality’ norm constitutes the ideal against which our existing insolvency law must be judged, since it enshrines desirable goals that any reasonable insolvency regime must attain. Deviations from pari passu are to be condemned for making the attainment of those goals more unlikely, and they are to be condemned even more precisely because they are so widespread. It is to this claim that we now turn.

 

3. The immunity/priority fallacy

For English lawyers, it seems the primary attraction of the pari passu principle is its ability to provide for an orderly liquidation. Goode makes the point firmly:

It is this principle of rateable distribution which marks off the rights of creditors in a winding up from their pre-liquidation entitlements. Prior to winding up each creditor is free to pursue whatever enforcement measures are open to him … The rule here, in the absence of an insolvency proceeding, is that the race goes to the swiftest … Liquidation puts an end to the race. The principle first come first served gives way to that of orderly realisation of assets by the liquidator for the benefit of all unsecured creditors and distribution of the net proceeds pari passu.63

Keay and Walton see the principle as the embodiment of similar virtues:

the whole idea of pari passu distribution is to ensure parity of benefit, no matter what resources one has—if there were no pari passu distribution we would return to the ‘first come, first served’ policy of mediaeval times, which saw those with the greatest resources and power taking the debtor’s estate.64

And for Finch the ‘equality’ principle ‘conduces to an orderly, collective means of dealing with unsecured creditor claims and [] involves lower distributional costs than alternative processes such as “first come, first served”.’65 For these commentators, the choice is clearly between a free-for-all where weak creditors would inevitably be beaten into last place by better-resourced competitors, and where (p.103) the advantages associated with an orderly liquidation would be lost, and the pari passu principle which alone stands as a bulwark against this.

What is more, and even given its less than universal efficacy, the pari passu principle is said to ‘retain [] some practical importance, if only in a negative sense, in that it may have the effect of invalidating pre-liquidation transactions by which a creditor hopes to secure an advantage over his competitors.’66 The principle is widely seen to be Very much at the heart of the rationale for the avoidance of pre-liquidation transactions’.67 Oditah notes that ‘In one sense, avoiding powers provide illustrations of insolvency laws commitment to the principle of equality.’68 And Goode observes that ‘the principle of equity among creditors which underlies the pari passu rule of insolvency law will in certain conditions require the adjustment of concluded transactions which but for the winding-up of the company would have remained binding on the company’.69

Given that the pari passu principle lies at the very heart of the orderly liquidation regime, and given its role in justifying some of the most distinctive and well-established aspects of insolvency law (its preference and other adjustment provisions), any deviations from it must naturally be considered odious at least prima facie. ‘Equality’ of treatment serves key practical and justificatory purposes which bring social benefits, so differential priority, its opposite, must result in a diminution of all those benefits. Those defending the priority (say) of secured claims must therefore bear a heavy burden of proof.

It is submitted that these arguments are based on a misunderstanding of the nature of the liquidation regime. All these arguments commit what will be referred to as the immunity/priority fallacy. Once that fallacy is exposed and exploded, the rationales given by those supporting the pari passu principle will be seen to provide no justification for it. And that principle in turn is shown not to play any role in bolstering the desirable properties of the liquidation regime.70

Let us start by understanding the distinction between priority and immunity.71 Recall again the old image, that of the debtor firm’s estate forming a pool of assets.

The first come first served concept

(p.104) As the firm approaches the stage where its assets are insufficient to meet its liabilities,72 and in the absence of a special liquidation regime, the firm’s creditors have an incentive to rush to enforce their claims. The earlier they can get a judgment and execute it, the more likely they would be to get paid in full, or at all. The tardy creditor would find that nothing is left for him, the pool already having been drained of all its contents. Further, and on the eve of insolvency, creditors aware of the firm's troubles and able to influence its decisions might try to steal the first drink from the asset pool by getting the debtor to repay them. Their gain is a collective loss. The ‘first come, first served’ system encourages creditors to engage in duplicative (hence wasteful) monitoring of their debtor in order not to be left behind in any race to the pool. It adds uncertainty and therefore decreases the utility of risk adverse creditors. And for the debtor whose assets are more valuable if disposed of together as a going concern, the individualistic system increases the possibility that those assets would be broken up nonetheless and sold piecemeal to satisfy claims as they arise.73 It is this value-destroying activity that the dedicated liquidation regime must prevent. Notice the cause of all the trouble: each creditor faces the necessity, and has the ability, to act individually, in disregard of the interests of all others. Hence the obvious solution: the dedicated liquidation regime is collective, decisions being taken on behalf of all those interested in the asset pool.

The analogy and the insight can be taken further. The individualistic pre-insolvency debt-collection regime is a mad race to the asset pool. Since that race is undesirable, the collective insolvency system steps in to stop it. The creditors are now forced to queue up to have access to the pool. Voidable preferences and post-petition dispositions of assets, etc. can now be seen as attempts by some creditors to bypass this queue. In other words, they represent efforts to gain immunity from the collective system. Insolvency law deploys various mechanisms to deny them this immunity.74 So long as there is no race to the pool, no one succeeds in stealing a drink from it, and creditors await their turn to have access to the debtor’s resources; decisions can be made systematically and in the common interest. Crucially, though, note that ensuring that creditors take their place in the queue is one thing. The order in which they line up is, in general, quite another. Each creditor's priority is their place in the queue relative to each other creditor. But espousing the aim that creditors all line up does not entail any particular order in which they should line up. It does not commit the system to placing all creditors (as it were) unidistant from the asset pool. The pari passu principle would put each (‘similar’) creditor side by side rather than (say) one after the other. But this arrangement is not a necessary concomitant to the absence of the value-destroying race. So long as there is a queue (with creditors standing side by side, one after the other, or in whatever order), there is no race.

(p.105) Consider now the various comments noted at the beginning of this section. It can be seen that they represent the immunity/priority fallacy. This can be defined as the attribution of the benefits resulting from the absence of immunity from a collective insolvency system, to an imaginary and irrelevant state of equal priority (the realm of pari passu). If the pre-insolvency ‘first come, first served’ system is objectionable in a firm’s insolvency, it is so because of the monitoring, uncertainty, administrative, and loss of synergetic value costs described above. All these costs result from an individualistic regime, and all of them are avoided by a collective one. As long as all those creditors whose actions would inflict those costs participate in the collective regime or submit to collective decision-making, how their claims are ranked relative to each other within the collective scheme of distribution is (for these purposes) irrelevant.75

Similarly, if certain attempts to gain preference are undesirable, that is because they undermine the benefits associated with collective decision-making.76 Consider the following situation. In the liquidation of a particular company, there is only one general unsecured creditor (say a trade creditor without the benefit of an effective ROT clause) and one preferential creditor (the Crown). Suppose the former engineers a (voidable) preference in her favour, so that both she and the preferential creditor finally get back the same proportion of their debts.77 Now the situation here simply cannot be objectionable on the basis that the pari passu rule has been breached. In fact, the outcome would probably be perfectly in accord with this rule, since the general creditor is likely to hold the same sort of non-insolvency claim as the preferential one. So if the rule applies, she should get back the same proportion of her debt as the latter. However, the voidable preference provisions have been violated nevertheless. So the pari passu principle could not possibly underlie these provisions, at least as they apply here. If this much is accepted, then the argument can be pressed further. It would not help to suggest that the principle justifies the preference avoidance provisions as they apply to a trade creditor who has been paid a greater proportion of his debt than another (say), but not when they apply to a trade creditor and an employee who both get the same proportion of what they are owed. To advocate this position would again be to create something of a paradox: that the need to provide ‘equal’ treatment legitimates the avoidance of a preference in the first situation, but actually providing such treatment constitutes the objectionable preference in the latter!

In fact, to understand the basis of the preference avoidance provisions, we must switch to the perspective suggested above. The party given the voidable preference (p.106) has been allowed to leave the place assigned to her by the insolvency system. She has been allowed to skip the queue for the insolvent’s assets. This is the factor which creates the preference.78 This example should make it clear that pari passu is not simply irrelevant to understanding the preference (and several other) avoidance provisions. In fact, the focus on the ‘equality’ principle can be positively misleading in this regard.79

 

4. The pari passu principle in action?

It is to be noted that the argument here is not one for a change in the law, for example to abolish the pari passu rule. The point is rather that the alleged manifestations of the principle are nothing of the sort. The law as it stands today is better understood by adopting the analysis in the previous section. That the veneration of the pari passu principle is false becomes clear when one examines some of the case-law said to support it.80 It must be emphasized that the only purpose of discussing these decisions is to show reliance on them in support of the pari passu principle is misguided. Note also that the order in which these cases are discussed is thematic, not historical.

Goode seems to cite Ex parte Mackay81 as authority for the proposition that ‘The pari passu rule may not be excluded by contract’.82 In this case, A and B entered into an agreement for A to sell a patent to B. B promised in return to pay (p.107) over to A the royalties received, and in addition, lent A £12,500. It was also agreed that, for satisfaction of this debt, B would have a lien over one-half of the royalties received, except if A became bankrupt, in which case B might retain all the royalties. A became bankrupt. It was held on appeal that the provision allowing for B to have additional security in the event of A’s bankruptcy was void as being a fraud on the bankrupt laws.83 Goode quotes the following parts of the judgment in support of the inexcludibility of the pari passu rule:

… a man is not allowed, by stipulation with a creditor, to provide for a different distribution of his effects in the event of bankruptcy from that which the law provides.84

… a person cannot make it a part of his contract that, in the event of his bankruptcy, he is then to get some additional advantage which prevents the property being distributed under the bankruptcy laws.85

However, neither of these dicta (nor any other portion of the judgments) make any reference to the pari passu principle. What they do indicate is, simply, that the bankrupt’s property is not to be distributed except under the rules of the bankruptcy system. Crucially, a creditor can not, even ex ante, ‘get some additional advantage’ in any way not itself allowed by that system. To resort to the analogy introduced above, he may not skip his assigned place in the queue, whatever that place might be. The decision provides absolutely no support for the very different proposition that under the liquidation system, the places assigned to creditors are all unidistant from the asset pool.86 Quite the reverse is in fact true. Remember that pari passu was almost as rare in practice at the time of this judgment as it is now. The decision must be seen against the background of a system which (for example) gave extensive preferences to the Crown, including by section 32 of the Bankruptcy Act 1869. The Crown also had statutory liens over various types of property by virtue of the different Excise Acts. And section 32 of the same Act had enhanced the pre-existing preference for certain debts owed to the bankrupt’s servants and clerks.87 In addition, section 39 of the Act provided for mandatory set-off in bankruptcy in the appropriate circumstances.88

(p.108) It should be clear that distribution according to the bankruptcy laws was not distribution pari passu. The bankruptcy laws did not place all creditors side by side. The ‘equality’ principle was part of that regime, but it was by no means the only part (it might not even have been the most important one). Note in addition, of course, that on the facts of this case, the priority provided to B by way of the lien over one-half of the royalties was upheld as perfectly proper in the same judgment.89 So to cite ex parte Maekay as an authority supporting only equal distribution is, with respect, quite wrong, since it is at least as much an authority for the prior inexcludibility of unequal treatment of claims, also provided for by the same laws. The only proposition this decision can be said to support is that one may not bargain for immunity from the collective bankruptcy regime (except as provided by the law).90

The sceptical reader should turn to National Westminster Bank Ltd. v. Halesowen Presswork and Assemblies Ltd.91 The House of Lords held (by a majority of three to one) that since the regime for the administration of insolvent estates embodies important elements of public policy, and since the rights of insolvency set-off form part of that regime, the creditor given such set-off rights can not contract out of them. This despite the fact that the agreement which precluded insolvency setoff, and which was struck down by their Lordships, seemed specifically to have been concluded (inter alia) to ensure that ‘certain large payments which were due to the [now-insolvent] company should be available for distribution pro rata amongst its creditors.’92 The liquidators view—that the party now asserting set-off should be ‘in no better position than any other creditor’ in the debtor company’s insolvency—was noted,93 but rejected.

So an exception to the ‘equality’ principle—the contractual disapplication of which might have led to a more ‘equal’ distribution—is as mandatory as any other part of the liquidation regime. What can not be contracted out of (in an unacceptable way) is not the pari passu principle, but the whole collective system for the winding-up of insolvent estates. Not only is it forbidden for a creditor to leave his (p.109) assigned place in the queue and step ahead of others, he can not even leave his place ahead of others and stand in line with them. The inequality inherent in the system (in this case by way of insolvency set-off) is every bit as binding as the equality. Note again that the focus is on attempts to frustrate (some of) the rules of the liquidation regime. Whether that would lead to an increase or decrease in the ‘equality’ of distribution is simply irrelevant.94

Consider British International Air Lines Ltd. v. Compagnie Nationale Air France.95 British Eagle (‘BE’) was a member of a clearing house scheme operated by the International Air Transport Association (‘lATA’). Sums due from participating airlines to each other were netted out at the end of every month. Those with a net credit balance would then receive a payment from the clearing house, while those with a net debit balance were required to pay into the system. BE having gone into liquidation, it was found that it owed money to various airlines, but had a claim against Air France (AF'). A bare majority of their Lordships allowed the liquidator to recover that sum on the basis that the netting arrangements contravened the pari passu principle. The Lords rejected AF’s contention that the liquidator’s only claim lay against the clearing house, and that it could only be for the amount (if any) which remained to BE’s credit after the netting-off. According to the majority, the netting arrangements captured for the benefit of the members of the clearing house an asset (the claim against AF) which, but for those arrangements, would have been available for distribution among BE’s general creditors.

That this case has been described as ‘[undoubtedly the] leading modern authority on the pre-eminence of thepari passu principle’96 is not without irony. The case could not possibly provide any support for the pari passuprinciple. Recall that this principle requires ‘equals’ to be treated ‘equally’.97 And the determination of ‘equality’ is generally left to non-insolvency law:

The Act of Parliament unquestionably says that everybody shall be paid pari passu, but that means everybody after the winding up has commenced. It does not mean that the Court shall look into past transactions, and equalise all the creditors … It takes them exactly as it finds them.98

But even Lord Cross, speaking for the majority, accepted that AF, and other members of the clearing house, were never equal to BE's general creditors outside (p.110) liquidation.99 During BE’s solvency, the members of IATA could not (unlike BE’s non-IATA creditors) just have ignored the clearing house arrangements and sued BE for any sums owed. Correspondingly, BE could not, while solvent, have jproceeded directly against AE It could only have claimed against the clearing house for any net balance due to it.100 And yet BE’s liquidator was allowed to do precisely what BE would not have been able to. By the same stroke, BE’s IATA creditors were forced to claim directly against BE (by proving in its liquidation) while they would have been neither required nor even allowed to do so before the commencement of its winding-up. Pre-insolvency unequals were forcibly equalised’ in insolvency This hardly constitutes a vindication of the pari passu principle, no matter what the judicial rhetoric. And in any case, the sums recovered as a result of this decision would not have been distributed pari passu. Pre-preferential and preferential creditors, etc. would have taken the first bite.101

Perhaps a better way of understanding the disputed issues in British Eagle would be to look at the netting arrangements simply as an attempt on the part of IATA to prevent its members from having to submit to the collective liquidation regime. Or at least this is how they seem to have been viewed by the majority of their Lordships.102 That such contracting-out (i.e. immunity) was not objectionable per was also accepted. Lord Cross implied that, had the IATA arrangements created charges in favour of the IATA creditors with effects equivalent to the disputed netting scheme, those would have been effective against the liquidator if duly registered.103 So the objection was not to the granting of immunity to only some of BE's creditors (or indeed to granting them priority over others). Rather, the majority were of the view that the advantages associated with recognising this novel way of acquiring immunity were not sufficient to outweigh (what they (p.111) saw as) the costs of such a significant derogation from the collective regime.104 This conceptualization of the majority's decision then also allows one to make sense or the strong dissenting speech by Lord Morris, who emphasized the benefits which flowed from having the netting arrangements.105 On the arguments made here, the thrust of the dissenting speeches would of course have to be that these benefits (of allowing the arrangements to prevail) would outweigh any associated costs.

Unfortunately, however, there seems to have been no suggestion in the arguments that the issue should be regarded thus, as a question of balancing the commercial advantages of recognizing this novel way of gaining immunity from the liquidation regime, against any lessening of the advantages associated with having a collective system. As already mentioned, the latter include the ability to preserve the going concern surplus if there is one, and the minimization of uncertainty, monitoring, and administrative costs. The IATA netting system should have been upheld if the costs to the actors resulting from any increases in uncertainty, monitoring, and administrative costs, in the risk that a going concern surplus would be lost, and in the diminution of the pool of assets entailed by the existence of immunity for LATA creditors, were outweighed by the benefits it brought to the same actors.106 (Note that this is a sufficient but not necessary condition, since the initial distribution scheme provided (p.112) by the liquidation regime is not self-evidently appropriate and therefore must itself be argued for.) The pari passu red herring served massively to confuse this issue. In failing to consider it clearly, it is submitted that the British Eagle decision is deeply unsatisfactory.107 Be that as it may, for the reasons discussed, the leading modern authority on the pre-eminence of the pari passu principle actually stands more for its hollowness than its hallowedness.

Ex parte Barter; Ex parte Black108 is another interesting decision cited in support of the pari passuprinciple.109 Simplifying the facts somewhat, X, a Portuguese steamship company, entered into an agreement with Y, who were shipbuilders. Under the agreement, Y were to build and sell to X a steamship, the price for which was to be paid in instalments as the construction work progressed. On payment of the first instalment, the agreement provided that the steamship, its engines, and all associated materials were to be vested in X, the buyers (the Court of Appeal referred to this as the Vesting clause’). It was also agreed that X would have the right to seize all these materials if the construction work remained discontinued for a specified period, or if the ship was not delivered on time, or if Y became insolvent or bankrupt (the ‘seizure clause’). Finally, the agreement stipulated that should any of the events mentioned above occur, X would have the right to employ alternative builders to complete the ship, and to use Y’s shipyard, premises, machinery, plant, tools, and any other materials present on Y’s premises suitable to the purpose (the ‘user clause’). The work commenced and the first instalment was paid. Subsequently, on Y’s insolvency, X exercised its rights under the ‘seizure clause’ and took possession of the ship, engines and related materials. This was upheld by the Court of Appeal: X was merely seizing property which already belonged to it by virtue of the ‘vesting clause’.110 However, the ‘user clause’ was struck down, since ‘a power upon bankruptcy to control the user after bankruptcy of property vested in the bankrupt at the date of the bankruptcy is invalid.’111

The Court’s decision is hardly surprising, in view of the extravagance of the terms of the ‘user clause’ if for no other reason.112 But in any case, the relevant issues are very clear on the facts. Note the two most important points. First and yet again, there was no absolute bar to the parties bargaining for immunity from the collective regime. This was quite obviously the effect of the ‘vesting’ and ‘seizure’ clauses. Instead of lining up with the rest of Y’s creditors and submitting to the collective decisions made by Y’s trustee, X was able to remove itself from the (p.113) queue to the extent of the value of the materials covered by the two clauses. But second, the user clause’ was an attempt to commandeer Y’s remaining estate for the sole benefit of X, removing that too from the ambit of the trustee’s decision-making.113 This was regarded as unjustifiable. Even as to the ‘user clause’, X had argued that it would redound to the general good of all of Y’s creditors, since the completion of the ship would reduce pro tanto the amount for which X would prove in the bankruptcy for Y’s breach of contract.114 The Court of Appeal disagreed: in the absence of the clause, the trustee would have decided whether to complete the ship and claim the contractual price, or to abandon the contract, and this decision would have been made for the benefit of all of Y’s creditors. But the ‘user clause’ removed the trustee’s ability to make that choice, and instead vested that choice in X.115 To the extent to which X was a creditor for damages for Y’s breach of contract, the clause purported to grant X immunity from having to participate in the collective bankruptcy regime. This attempt to gain immunity was regarded as unacceptable.

Now whatever one might think of the distinctions made in the Court’s judgment about acceptable and unacceptable ways of by-passing the collective regime, note once again that the pari passu principle was not at issue. The ‘user clause’ would have by-passed the inequality of the regime (inherent in the rules governing set-off, pre-preferential and preferential claims, etc.) before it evaded its ‘equality’. The crucial issue was not X’s place in the queue relative to other creditors but the fact that he would not have had to queue up at all, and—if that was not enough—would have prevented the trustee being able to make a collective decision about much of the remaining pool of assets.116

The same point can be made again and again. Cases cited in support of the ‘equality’ principle either support that principle only as part of a significantly ‘unequal’ insolvency regime, or more frequently, show nothing except the law’s intolerance towards attempts to gain immunity from the collective liquidation system in unacceptable or unfamiliar ways. In view of all this, the pari passu principle could not possibly be necessary for there to be an orderly liquidation. In addition to all the arguments above, to the extent that the current liquidation regime is accepted as fulfilling the requirements of orderliness and as replacing the value-destroying rush for an insolvent’s assets, and given that pari passu is a very (p.114) partial feature of the system, the present liquidation regime itself constitutes a rebuttal of any such claim.117 What is more, the very significant departure from this principle represented by insolvency set-off has been regarded at the highest judicial level as itself necessary for a ‘proper and orderly’ administration of the estates of insolvent companies.118 But then, since ‘equal’ treatment of different types of claim is not required to gain the practical advantages associated with the orderly winding up of insolvent estates, and since it is not necessary to justify insolvency law’s peculiar features (e.g. its collectivity, and the avoidance of preferences and post-petition dispositions), the existence of differential priority—including that of secured creditors—can not be impugned on the ground that it interferes with the attainment of these goals.

Finally and in the interests of completeness, a decision which allows parties to bargain for a priority different from the one they would have had without that agreement—but without allowing immunity from the rules of the liquidation regime—is Re Maxwell Communications Corporation.119 This case concerned an agreement whereby certain bonds issued by M Ltd. (held by parties referred to hereafter as ‘the Bondholders’) were guaranteed by M Plc. ‘on a subordinated basis’. Subsequently, M Ltd. being insolvent, M Plc. was placed in administration. The administrator applied for an order to exclude the Bondholders from participation in a scheme of arrangement under which, secured and preferential creditors having been paid, the remainder would be distributed pari passu among M Plc.’s other unsecured creditors. In accordance with the subordination agreement, the Bondholders would only be paid if these other unsecured creditors were first paid off in full. It was clear on the facts that, if this scheme was approved, the Bondholders would get nothing.120

It was argued on behalf of the Bondholders that the subordination agreement was void as being in breach of thepari passu principle: ‘the liquidator ought not to be required or entitled to look behind a proof to determine whether a creditor submitting a proof was entitled to payment pari passu with other unsecured creditors ’121 In effect, the submission was that the pari passu principle should be (p.115) given effect with respect to all those general creditors who submitted a proof, the liquidator being required to turn a blind eye to the pre-insolvency dealings between the debtor and (some of) its creditors. This was rejected. Vinelott J pointed out that ‘There are situations under the Insolvency Act 1986 in which an unsecured debt is postponed to other unsecured debt.’122In these situations, the liquidator might well need to have regard to the pre-insolvency status of different unsecured creditors. So if the liquidator had no difficulty in determining the pre-insolvency positions of various unsecured creditors and giving effect to statutory subordination, he would face no greater hurdle in dealing with contractual subordination.123 The judge read British Eagle as laying down the rule that ‘a creditor cannot validly contract with his debtor that he will enjoy some advantage in a bankruptcy or winding-up which is denied to other creditors.’ However, he held that this did not preclude an agreement between A and B Ltd. for the latter’s debt to A to be subordinated in B’s insolvency to that owed to B’s other unsecured creditors.124

For the reader who is still not convinced, this decision should make it clear that the pari passu principle is far from sacrosanct. It is obvious that Re Maxwell allows parties to avoid it. The Bondholders, who would have ranked pari passu with M Plc.’s other creditors, were relegated because of the terms of their agreement with M Plc. to a position inferior to those other creditors. But this aspect of the decision should not tempt one to the hasty conclusion that the inexcludibility confirmed by British Eagle ‘applie[s] only to those rules the infringement of which would give one creditor an advantage denied to other creditors.’125 Resorting once again to the analogy of the common pool, this would amount to saying that the rule is that within the insolvency regime, one can contract out of one’s assigned place in the queue if the result would be to increase the insolvency value available for the remaining unsecured creditors,126 but not if it would decrease that value. But this interpretation would be quite inconsistent with the House of Lords’ judgment in Natwest v. Halesowen.127That case shows that one is not allowed to change one’s place in the queue for the pool of the insolvent’s assets simply because that would increase the insolvency share of the remaining creditors. As already noted, the Lords there struck down an agreement which, by altering a creditor’s priority position, would have brought about just such an increase.128

(p.116) So when should parties be allowed to change their priority position within the collective liquidation regime, in other words, to alter their relative places in the queue to the pool of the insolvent's assets? Most obviously, an agreement to alter the priority position of creditors within the liquidation regime should be allowed when—for all the creditors whose priority position in their debtor’s insolvency would be made worse off because of the agreement—the expected overall benefits of the agreement (i.e. not merely those accruing if and when the debtor does become insolvent) to those same creditors outweigh its expected overall costs.129 (This again is a sufficient but not necessary condition, and is discussed further in the next section.) More abstractly, it is submitted that such an agreement must be upheld if it would be sanctioned by principles acceptable to all the affected parties bargaining with each other in the choice position of the Authentic Consent Model (‘ACM’).130

5. Fairness as ‘equality’

We have considered—and rejected—the claim that the ‘equality’ principle is essential for the orderly liquidation of companies, and that it underlies important and distinctive features of the collective insolvency regime. This section challenges the other main role often assigned to it. The pari passu principle requires that all creditors (in positions of relative equality as determined by pre-insolvency law) should be paid back the same proportion of their debt in their debtor’s liquidation. Since this type of ‘equality’ represents fairness, runs this argument, the pari passu rule ensures that all creditors are treated fairly. Keay and Walton are of the view that ‘The underlying aim behind the use of the equality principle is to produce fairness, so that every creditor is treated in the same way.’131 As noted above, they argue that to abolish this principle would be to return to the ‘mediaeval’ policy of allowing those with the greatest resources and power to deprive poorer and weaker creditors of everything in their debtor's insolvency.132 This would be normatively unattractive. Several other commentators have suggested in a similar vein that the ‘equality’ principle enshrines fairness in liquidation.133

(p.117) The debate about equality as a political ideal is complex and ongoing.134 The discussion here will have to be quite a summary one. However, it is respectfully suggested that even this should suffice, at the very least, to cast serious doubt on the claim that the pari passu principle conduces to fairness in liquidation.

There can be no doubt that real equality is a—some would say the only—form of fairness. But a set of laws enshrines real equality only when it treats all those subject to it as equals. However, ‘There is a difference between treating people equally, with respect to one or another commodity or opportunity, and treating them as equals.’135 It is this crucial distinction which is universally overlooked by supporters of the pari passuprinciple.

Let us distinguish, in a rough and ready way, between formal and real equality. In the relevant context, formal equality holds when the same rule applies to all people. That everyone must stop at a red traffic light is an example. This type of equality, while undoubtedly important, results in a fairly superficial form of fairness, the limits of which are easy to expose. It is not obviously fair to insist that an ambulance should be obliged to wait at the red signal just like any other vehicle, even though carrying a seriously ill patient. That access to a building is provided ‘equally’ to all by way of a steep staircase does not necessarily prevent those using wheelchairs from being treated unfairly Or think of a flat-rate income tax: regardless of how much you earn, let us say 25 per cent of your annual income is to be paid over to the State. Many (perhaps most) readers would intuitively find this method of taxation normatively unappealing. That you are to be deprived of the same proportion of your income, whether you earn £10,000 or £10 m per annum, would not strike them as particularly fair. Note here the parallel with the pari passu rule, which represents the decision that all creditors are to be deprived of the same proportion of their debts, should their debtor become insolvent. The problem is that a rule based on formal equality does not take into account important differences between people, even though those differences are relevant to any consideration of the rule’s fairness. Of course equals must be treated as equals, but who is to be considered equal to whom, and in what respect? Merely formal equality might resolve these vital questions by reference to trivial, or irrelevant, or meaningless attributes. But for equality to result in fairness (a morally charged concept), the determination of who (p.118) constitutes an equal must be based on characteristics which themselves are morally significant. So in important ways, a rule based on formal equality is empty of normative content. To treat people with only formal equality often is not to treat them as equals.

How do we treat people, then, in order to treat them as equals? One attempt to describe what this entails in the specific context of corporate insolvency is of course the ACM,136 and we can bring this to bear upon the analysis of the status of the pari passu principle. The peculiar insolvency issue is the distribution of assets in a corporate liquidation, and the proposal is that all those who hold a claim which non-insolvency law determines to be formally similar, are to get back the same proportion of what they are owed. Would the parties in the choice position, bargaining in Dramatic Ignorance about the governing principles appropriate to this situation, be tempted by formal equality of this sort?137 It is submitted that they would not. The reason is straightforward. Non- in solvency law does not need to determine the priority status of different types of creditor, since for most solvent debtors, all creditors get everything they are owed.138 For that reason, non-insolvency law makes few formal distinctions between various types of claimant. The unsecured claim of a bank, a tax liability owed to the Crown, and the unpaid wages of an unskilled worker, all have the same pre-insolvency form. Non-insolvency law often does not resolve an issue which is (almost by definition) peculiar to insolvency itself—who should bear how much loss when a company is rendered terminally unable to meet its obligations?139 So when an actor does become insolvent, to seek guidance from non-insolvency law to determine how different claimants ought to be treated—as the pari passu principle purports to do—is to commit the old formalist error identified above. The ‘equality’ principle determines who counts as an ‘equal’ by reference to an attribute of the claimants (i.e. the non-insolvency form of their claim) which is irrelevant or meaningless as regards the appropriateness of any method of distribution of an insolvents estate.

Here is a simple demonstration that parties conceived of as equals would not choose the pari passu rule. Let us isolate the issues of interest to us by making three assumptions. First, suppose there are only four types of creditor: commercial banks, the Crown, weak trade creditors,140 and the debtor’s employees. Second, we also ignore for the moment the employee-creditors’ rights under the (p.119) Employment Rights Act 1996.141 And finally, pretend that the parties in the choice position are allocating the bankrupts estate without reference to their own pre-insolvency interests and commitments.142 In Dramatic Ignorance, parties do not know whether they would turn out to be an employee, or to have their relevant interests represented by a bank or the Crown. They are aware, though, that banks lend to thousands of companies (or more) and are therefore well-diversified. Banks can balance the harm of receiving somewhat less in the insolvency of some of their debtors, against the profit they make from lending to the many more who pay back every penny with interest. By virtue of being repeat players, they have accumulated expertise in assessing the credit-worthiness of their borrowers. And since they are strong commercial players in an under-diversified market for the provision of credit,143 they have a strong influence on the terms on which they lend. So bank-creditors are very well placed to deal with being paid back less than they are owed in any individual insolvency.

On the other hand, employee-creditors might often be dependent solely on their salaries, might be unable to diversify by working for more than one employer, might have no insurance because they are not able to join a trade union which would buy such insurance for its members, might have had no influence over the terms on which they were employed and therefore became creditors, and might be unable quickly to find work on being deprived of a job by virtue of their employer's insolvency.144 Employees might be owed wages for several weeks or months, having supplied services to their company while it was in financial distress without demanding payment on time, in the hope that the company would recover. Such employee-creditors might suffer serious detriment if they were to lose too great a proportion of their outstanding debts.

In the choice position of the ACM, parties bargaining about the appropriate rule for the distribution of the insolvent’s assets would find the suggestion that bank-creditors and employee-creditors both be treated ‘equally’ by being paid back the same proportion of what they are owed, simply absurd. That the two types of creditor hold claims judged under non-insolvency law to be formally similar to each other would not carry too much weight. The parties do not know whether they would turn out to be (or to be represented by) bank- or employee-creditors, so they accord equal concern to the sets of interests associated with each. But this requires that those in a more vulnerable position in their debtor’s insolvency be given greater protection than those better able to deal with the loss. Knowing that they could deal quite well with being paid back less on any (p.120)individual loan if they turned out to be represented in the real world by a bank, all the parties would agree to provide greater protection to employee-claimants, just in case they found themselves vulnerable to great harm as one themselves. The construction of the choice position allows us to see this as one morally relevant factor here. Fairness does not result from treating the two types of creditor ‘equally’, so the pari passu principle would be rejected outright as applied to bank-and employee-creditors with claims similar to each other under non-insolvency law. The same reasoning holds mutatis mutandis for the various types of creditor different in this morally significant way, regardless of the formal legal nature of their claims. So for example, the principles of distribution resulting from this exercise are more likely to give employee-creditors at least a degree of priority in their employer’s insolvency over most other types of claimant.145

Note that the extent to which creditors are vulnerable to serious harm in their debtor’s insolvency is only one of several relevant considerations for the parties in the choice position. The point here is not to identify all such factors (or even to defend the preferential debts regime as it stands today), but rather, to cast doubt on the pari passu principle as the guardian of fairness in liquidation. It should be obvious its crude ‘equality’ is almost entirely unattractive to parties treated as equals.

What about the alleged additional role of the pari passu principle, that it applies within the categories of creditor created by insolvency law itself? Some of the problems with this suggestion were noted in the first section of this chapter. But most importantly, this interpretation of the principle again can make no reference to fairness. Consider the example of the special reserve fund, against which claims held both by the Crown and by the weak trade creditors are to be vindicated. Again reasoning subject to the three assumptions stated above, there can be no question of the parties in the choice position accepting the same treatment for these two types of creditor. Weak trade creditors, somewhat like employee-creditors, are often unable to influence the terms on which they lend, and are also bad monitors of their debtor’s financial prospects. So the parties in the choice position might be minded to pay attention to an argument that the claims held by such trade creditors should be accorded some priority. However, there is little that can be said on the grounds identified so far for the Crown to enjoy the same priority as them. While the Crown does not choose its debtors, it is still maximally diversified (by being the universal creditor within its domain) and obviously therefore, is able to absorb a greater share of the loss than employee-creditors. Unlike them, it also has the ability to vary the rates at which it lends’, and can decide for itself how to use that ability. For example, it could put in place a mechanism to judge the risk of non-payment by some of its debtors, and to charge rates of interest on due but unpaid taxes accordingly.146 For the parties bargaining in (p.121) Dramatic Ignorance, its decision not to do so does not render it any more worthy of protection. It also has access to privileged information about its debtors, and enjoys immense economies of scale in keeping track of their financial prospects. Such mechanisms are of course not even remotely available to weak trade creditors. It should be clear that even if the parties decided the Crown should receive some sort of preference over creditors who choose their debtors freely, this priority would be likely to be lower than that accorded to the sort of trade creditors described above. ‘Equality’ does not conduce to fairness even within the category of those able to press claims against the special reserve fund, since these two types of claimant are notequal in crucial ways.147

This concludes the argument that the pari passu principle has little to do with fairness. But to leave the discussion at this point would be profoundly misleading. Recall the third assumption made above, that parties deciding on the choice of principles to govern distribution of an insolvent’s assets are unconcerned about theirpre-insolvency rights and obligations. This assumption allowed us to focus narrowly on whether ‘equality’ of distribution in corporate liquidation is normatively attractive. But while useful for that purpose, this assumption is problematic and of course entirely counterfactual. Creditors of a firm which becomes insolvent do not suddenly develop a completely new set of interests without link or connection with the interests they had before this particular debtor became unable to pay its debts. In their capacity as actors on the commercial stage, they do not undergo a rebirth which purges them of pre-insolvency commitments. Their interests and obligations within liquidation flow from their pre-liquidation ones, and the former are inextricably linked to the latter. So for example, to accept the very existence of claims against the now-insolvent company is to acknowledge this inseverable link with the pre-insolvency commitments of the actors. And one of the reasons why employees are more deserving of protection in their employer’s insolvency is their pre-insolvency inability to diversify, and (for many employees) to have an appreciable say about the terms of their employment, etc.

It follows that, while the pre-insolvency form of claims might not matter, the pre-insolvency interests and obligations of all the parties must always be taken into consideration when deciding about the priority of certain types of claimant over others. Fairness demands that each claimant be accorded equal care and concern. But this involves looking at the totality of the interests and obligations of each. So the principles of insolvency law, though dealing exclusively with peculiar insolvency issues, should not focus exclusively on the interests of parties once a relevant actor is already insolvent. Rather, they should affect the parties in a way which pays equal attention to both their pre- and post-insolvency interests and obligations, conceived of as the continuities that they actually are.

(p.122) In the ACM, the parties may be Dramatically Ignorant, but they are not hemianopic.148 They do not lose sight of their own pre-insolvency lives (though none of them knows which of these lives is their’s). They realize that actors in the real world often interact with each other in the shadow of insolvency law. So they select those principles to be part of that law which would uphold any pre-insolvency priority arrangements which, for example, serve the entirety of the interests of each of them. This despite the fact that those arrangements do not serve the post-insolvency interests of some of them.149

So parties in Dramatic Ignorance might approve principles of insolvency law which allow Creditor A and Debtor to agree that in Debtor’s liquidation, A would rank higher than Creditor B. They would accept this situation even though each of them has an equal chance—as against each other party—of turning out to be B. This is because the agreement to grant A priority might nevertheless bring B greater, countervailing benefits, for example by reducing the risk that their mutual debtor would become insolvent in the first place. And parties in the choice position care about their non-insolvency lives as much as about their post-insolvency ones, since (because of the construction of Dramatic Ignorance) they do not know if their debtor would in fact become insolvent. So one of insolvency law’s more challenging tasks is to distinguish between pre-insolvency priority arrangements which are mutually advantageous to all the relevant parties, and those which are merely exploitative.150 The latter must of course be ruled out, but it would conduce to fairness actually to give effect to the unequal distribution resulting from the former.151

We should note the implications. The fact that creditor X receives 10 per cent of his claim in the winding-up of its debtor and creditor Y receives 50 per cent is, by itself, no reason at all for reaching any conclusion on the appropriateness of the result. One must peer behind these figures, since they are meaningless in isolation.152Similarly, arguments which, for example, bemoan the fact that there are so many security and quasi-security devices that little is left for distribution to (p.123) unsecured creditors in their debtor’s insolvency, are by themselves of little consequence in the debate about the fairness of according priority to secured claims. That the liquidator in most proceedings has little to dole out to certain types of creditor may or may not be regrettable. For an answer, we would have to sift through the totality of dealings amongst all the concerned parties. We might find, as a result, that the existence of priority for secured claims does lead to the exploitation of unsecured creditors, or to other undesirable consequences. But that conclusion is not an a priori truth, nor can it be discovered simply by looking at the treatment in insolvency proceedings alone of unsecured creditors.153

This discussion provides normative support for Dalhuisen’s observation that:

The equality of creditors is often presented as a justified concern and as an argument against the [priority implications of ] the proprietary effects of all kinds of financial schemes … However, this equality … is not truly the basis of the system of creditors’ protection or a fundamental legal principle, although endlessly paraded as such. If it were, it would only be honoured in the breach and it distorts the discussion. In my researches of bankruptcy law I have always found that it is equitable, not equal, distribution that is the key, and what is equitable in this respect is now mostly a matter of statutory definition in domestic bankruptcy acts.154

In the terms adopted here, what matters is real equality of treatment of all the creditors (in other words, that they be treated ‘equitably’), not formal equality. The next section asks in what circumstances the latter is and should be resorted to.

6. The role of ‘equality’

The argument so far has concentrated on what the pari passu principle in particular, and formal equality in general, do not do. It would perhaps be useful to add a word here about what is in fact their actual role. Formal equality operates in three types of situations in liquidation, always for the same reason. First, consider the pari passu principle itself. Commonly understood as governing the claims of general unsecured creditors, it is submitted that this is not primarily a rule of distribution at all. To the contrary, it is a rule of non-distribution. The argument here can be broken down into four steps.

First, certain types of claim are considered ‘important’, in the sense that they should be met to a significant degree in most insolvencies. To ensure that this is the case, they are allotted special priority positions, either by the parties to commercial transactions, or (where the parties cannot be trusted to reach the right result) by Parliament itself Second, not to provide a particular priority position for a type of claim is to ensure it will receive little or nothing in most insolvencies.

(p.124) Third and following from that, there must still be a fall-back provision which covers the treatment of these latter claims. In view of the paucity of value to be distributed to those holding such claims, it is especially important that the implementation of this fall-back provision be cost-effective. The conclusion is that the pari passu principle is the ideal fall-back provision. This is the basic structure of the argument, and it must now be fleshed out.

Note once again that in any formal insolvency proceeding, different claims are treated according to different priority rules, depending both on who holds those claims, and the sort of assets to which the claims are being applied. Creditors able to assert set-off rights created and mandated by insolvency law beat all others to the extent of those rights. Assets subject to fixed charges are governed by the appropriate priority rules.155 The trade creditor with the benefit of an acceptable ROT provision can reclaim the goods supplied. For property subject only to a floating charge, parties holding claims arising after the initiation of a formal insolvency proceeding rank ahead of preferential creditors who rank ahead of the claims of unsecured creditors (up to the full value of the special reserve fund) who in turn rank before the floating charge holder, and so on. All these priority rules are thought to have different rationales. For example, insolvency set-off is said to be based on consideration of fairness.156 The priority of (some) secured creditors arguably stems from strong efficiency considerations and being mutually advantageous to all, would be upheld by parties bargaining in the ACM’s choice position.157Post-liquidation creditors are given precedence because they can not be expected to subsidise pre-existing claimants. Preferential creditors are said to be worthy of special treatment because they do not choose their debtor in any meaningful sense, do not negotiate the terms of their loans, and (in the case of employees) might be undiversified.158 The creation of the special reserve fund reflects the conviction that unsecured creditors are more worthy of protection from the loss flowing from insolvency than are the holders of claims secured by a floating charge (qua floating charge holder159). The list goes on. The different priority rules are all complex. It takes time, resources and effort for Parliament on the one hand, and debtors and creditors themselves on the other, to decide what types of claim should rank in what order, with respect to different types of asset.

Of course, however, the state of insolvency is by definition one where the debtor can not fulfil all its obligations. (As already suggested, priority rules are really crucial only against this background of insolvency.) Neither Parliament nor commercial parties themselves have provided specific rules of distribution for that (p.125)portion of unsecured claims not capable of being vindicated against the special reserve fund. View this in the context that generally, only secured, post-liquidation and preferential creditors get anything in their debtor’s insolvency. There is little or (much more frequently) nothing for those ranking below them.160 So the interests regarded as more worthy of attention (and therefore arguably more important) by the rule-makers (public and private) are given precedence with respect to particular types of asset, in certain situations, to a specified extent. To decide not to provide for such a priority for a type of claim is in fact to decide not to have it met at all in most insolvencies. And it is this reasoning which provides the crucial insight into the true role of the ‘equality’ norm. It was suggested above that pari passu should not be viewed as a default rule. It can not accurately be regarded as the starting position, departures from which must be explained. Instead, it is now submitted, the rule is best seen as a fall-back provision. It is the rule which takes over when it would be pointless to provide any other.

Look at the argument again. Some types of claim are regarded as important, and rules are provided to govern how they should be dealt with in insolvency. But once this is done, nothing (or not much) would be left for distribution to other creditors. Recall that most insolvency proceedings (75 per cent of them or more) yield nothing for general unsecured creditors. And when they do bring some returns, the yields are fairly small (about 7 pence on the pound on average). So there simply is no point in deciding how these claims should rank vis-à-vis each other. For such claims to be governed by the pari passu rule makes very good sense, since the costs in terms of time, effort, and resources required to determine their appropriate (fair and efficient) rankings would far exceed any benefits. Why waste resources identifying and laying down different priorities, when it is obvious hardly any assets are likely to be distributed according to them? For such a situation, in fact, ‘equal’ treatment is ideal. In most instances, this simply means some types of creditor equally get nothing. In the remaining minority of insolvencies, the tiny amounts available for distribution are all distributed proportionately, rather than being wasted in ascertaining the claimants’ correct rankings. The pari passu principle applies, then, whenever the costs of providing for different rankings for different claims would exceed the benefits.161 The claims it governs mostly—and necessarily—constitute something approaching a distributively null set; they are held by those who will not receive anything. If they do receive something, it would not be much.

Now for the second application of formal equality in corporate liquidation, which lies in the treatment of the same ‘type’ of claimant. For example, claims of all employees are treated ‘equally’ and given preferential treatment over most other (p.126) unsecured creditors. It was argued above that employees might be more deserving of protection in their employer’s insolvency than other types of creditor, since they are more vulnerable to greater harm in these circumstances. But of course this is not equally true of all employees. It is not obvious that computer engineers, software designers, commercial lawyers, and others with scarce skills are in need of the same protection as unskilled workers. And one Information Technology expert might be much better placed to deal with the insolvency of his employer than another, perhaps because the former is younger and therefore considered more (re-)employable in that young industry.

But it makes sense nevertheless to treat all of them the same, simply because it would be too expensive to require the liquidator to investigate the relative positions of all the claimants in terms of vulnerability to serious detriment. What is more, it would be next to impossible for her to determine whether a particular employee was more vulnerable than others in this insolvency because, for example, he had been less cautious in planning for such a contingency than all the others, or because he had more expensive tastes for consumables like holidays, etc.162 Most liquidators asked to embark upon such an exercise would necessarily exhaust all available assets along the way, and no one would get anything. Apart from being inefficient, wastage of this nature does not lead to fairness either.163 Again, then, ‘equality’ is resorted to because the costs of employing any more appropriate method of distribution (including one which is fairer in the abstract) would outweigh its benefits.164

(p.127) Before the coming into force of the Enterprise Act 2002, a third manifestation of formal equality used to hold between preferential tax and preferential employee claims. As already noted, tax claim preferences have now been abolished. However, an analysis of this type of formal equality nevertheless proves illuminating. Notionally, of course, employees and the Crown were the two types of preferential claimant. But the employees of an insolvent firm, in recognition of their especially vulnerable position, have been accorded rights which—in their capacity as creditors—make them rather less concerned about their employer's insolvency. This is because of the provisions of what is now the Employment Rights Act 1996 CERA). This regime ‘provides for different and generally more extensive protection for an employee than under the Insolvency Act.’165 Under it, the Secretary of State, through the Redundancy Payment Service, makes payments to employees from the National Insurance Fund. The ERA scheme covers (inter alia) up to eight weeks of unpaid wages and salaries, wages during the statutory minimum notice period, up to six weeks of holiday pay, and a basic award for unfair dismissal. These payments are likely to be larger than those given preferential status by the Insolvency Act. For the payments made, the Secretary of State is subrogated to the employees’ rights.166

Relevant to our discussion is the fact that, ‘once employees’ rights under ERA are factored into the overall picture, [] the Crown, by subrogation, takes over the claims of employees in a very large proportion of cases and is often the sole preferential creditor.'167 Again, then, we have an excellent explanation (though historically perhaps a partial one) for the fact that preferential tax claims used to rank ‘equally’ with preferential ‘employee’ claims. Most of these claims were held by the same actor, the Crown. So again it would simply have been pointless to provide for different priorities for these claims. Why expend resources differentiating these claims both ex ante and ex post, when in most cases any such differentiation would merely have been nominal? It is submitted that this provides further support for the proposition that formal equality in insolvency law (including that enshrined in the pari passu rule) is resorted to only when the costs of providing otherwise would outweigh the benefits. It is for this reason that the pari passu principle is best regarded as a fall-back provision. It is submitted that it plays no other role in insolvency distributions.168

Finally, note that even if analytically accurate, this claim is incomplete from a historical perspective. To plug this gap, here is one hypothesis. The search costs for ascertaining optimum rankings for different types of claim depend either on (p.128) the availability of a theory of finance, or on a process of trial-error-adjustment by the parties themselves. When the former method is unavailable or underdeveloped, the time component of search costs (incurred during trial-error-adjustment) is high.169 So initially, only the more obvious methods of distribution (e.g. pari passu), and of bargaining for priority (e.g. rudimentary forms of security), which have therefore been developed earlier and employed for longer, would be cost-effective. So after 1543, when statute first provided for claims against bankrupts to be paid in ‘a portion rate and rate like, according to the quantity of their debt’,170 this initially might in fact have been a rule of almost universal application, perhaps only secured and Crown claims being exempt.171 Again, this would have been so not because Parliament and the parties themselves at that time were fairer than they are now, but simply because no better method of distribution had then been discovered (i.e. none was cost-effective). But as better (fairer and more efficient) methods were discovered both through trial-error-adjustment and the development of theories of finance, pari passu would quickly be relegated to a mere fall-back provision even as applied to unsecured claims.

This hypothesis predicts that unless all creditors in real life are truly equal in all relevant respects, there would always be an increasing tendency for a fair and efficient insolvency law system to develop different priorities for different types of claim, to the full extent of all the assets generally available in liquidation.172 This then implies that attempts to ‘equalise’ distributions to creditors who are different in relevant respects are misguided, since they impede the development of a fairer and more efficient system.

7. The removal of tax claims preferences

The analysis in the previous section allows us to examine the recent removal of the preferential status enjoyed by certain tax claims (discussed above).173 This step (p.129) was conceived of as ‘an important and integral part’ of a package of reforms to corporate insolvency law, which also included the virtual abolition of administrative receivership and changes to the administration procedure to make it more ‘streamlined’, and thus the successor to receivership. The Government predicted that the removal of tax claim preferences would bring ‘major benefits to trade and other unsecured creditors, including small businesses’.174 Importantly, however, the preferential status of ‘employee’ claims was retained, ‘as [were] the rights of those subrogated to them’.175 It will be argued in this section that the removal of the preferential status of tax claims is unlikely to bring any significant benefit to unsecured creditors, and thus may not fulfil its stated objective. In addition, the manner in which the categories of preferential claims have been reformed lacks coherence.

In order to evaluate the effects of the abolition of tax claim preferences, we should begin by trying to estimate the quantum of the additional benefits to unsecured creditors which can be expected to result from its implementation. Even a very rough estimate requires a lengthy calculation, and because of the imprecision of the data available, the estimate here will indeed be rough. But it will soon become apparent that this does not matter to the point being made here. Unless otherwise stated, any doubts in the figures are resolved so as to maximize the expected additional benefit to unsecured creditors from the proposed change.

At the moment, total liabilities of companies that undergo a formal insolvency procedure during a year are estimated to be about £42b.176 Of this, about 35 per cent is owed to banks.177 Let us suppose that 80 per cent of bank debt is secured by the company’s assets.178 So secured creditors are owed, roughly, 28 per cent of the total outstanding debt. Preferential creditors get back about 30 per cent of what they are owed.179 The amount actually paid out as dividends in right of tax claims preferences is around £ 100m.180 So preferential tax claims themselves amount to some £333m. The amount owed in right of employee preferences is an estimated £200m.181 Altogether, then, preferential debts constitute about 1.3 per cent of the total debts owed by insolvent companies. It follows that (p.130) unsecured creditors are owed about 70.7 per cent of the total outstanding debt of companies in insolvency proceedings. This amounts to around £29.69b. They get an average of 7 pence on the pound,182 or about £2. lb (£2100m) today.

Now the Government estimates that the removal of tax claims preferences would bring ‘up to’ £100m more for unsecured creditors.183 So after the removal of preferential status for tax claims, unsecured creditors can be expected to receive £2,200m.184 In other words, their recoveries should go up to 7.4 per cent once the proposal is implemented. This is of course an increase of less than one-half of one penny over what they currently get! And that does not take into account that all tax claims would then also rank alongside other unsecured claims (and would be vindicated against the special reserve fund).185

It should be obvious, then, that even if these calculations are wide of the mark (so that the actual increase will be twice, thrice, or even five times this much), the average recovery rates for unsecured creditors in an overwhelming majority of formal insolvency proceedings are unlikely to go up to the extent that such creditors would be appreciably better off. The Government’s claim that this ‘important and integral’ part of its reform package will bring ‘major benefits’ to them therefore seems somewhat implausible.186 In addition, and in line with the analysis in the previous sections, it should be noted that it makes very obvious sense to subject to a distributive rule based on formal equality the tiny additional sums which will become available in many formal insolvency proceedings because of the proposed change. For these additional sums, it would be entirely wasteful to attempt to think up some other set of priorities. The costs of doing that would be quite unjustified in view of the size of the expected benefits.187

(p.131) So much for the suggestion that the change is likely to be inefficacious. To understand why its implementation is incoherent, we should recall that because of the rights of employee-creditors of insolvent companies under the ERA, the claims apparently held by them and given preferential status, are mostly vested in the Crown by way of subrogation. So preferential tax claims and preferential ‘employee’ claims are in most cases held by the same actor. Nor did this fact go unnoticed in the White Paper. As already mentioned, the Paper not only stated that certain employee claims would retain their preferenrial status, but also explicitly included within this reservation ‘the rights of those subrogated to them’,188 or in other words, of the Crown itself. Now the supposed rationale for removing the preferential status of tax claims is presumably the well-rehearsed one that the Crown is better able to absorb the loss of not being paid by some of its debtors, than are some other categories of creditor, for example, weak trade creditors.189 But if this is accepted, it surely follows that ‘employee’ claims, also generally held by the Crown, should have lost their preferential status for exactly the same reason. Employees might deserve greater protection in their employers insolvency than other types of claimant, but if they have already been reimbursed from the National Insurance Fund, then the competition is no longer between them and other unsecured creditors, but between the latter and the Crown. So there seems little sense in abolishing only one category of preferential claims, when the reason why that change was considered desirable is equally a reason to reform the other category as well. This is especially relevant given that the stated aim of improving the prospects of unsecured creditors is expected to be fulfilled to a negligible degree in any case.190

At the very least, the Government bore the burden of showing what makes preferential tax claims different from most preferential ‘employee’ claims. One way in which it might have attempted to do so would have been to provide better data than are currently available in order to rebut the premise of this argument, that the Crown holds, by subrogation, most preferential ‘employee’ claims. But even then, the obvious solution would have been to adopt the approach enshrined in the US Bankruptcy Code, which provides that an entity subrogated to the rights of, inter alia, the employee-creditors of a bankrupt company, is not entitled to enjoy the statutory preferential status provided to some of their claims.191 This would have ensured that the preferential stattis of ‘employee’ debts was retained only to the extent that employees themselves would benefit from it. Since the Government has failed to explain why this was considered unacceptable, it seems difficult to avoid the conclusion that its approach to this issue was based on an arbitrary and thus unjustifiable distinction.

(p.132) 8. Conclusion

Some years ago, Bridge concluded his brief review of the clash between pari passu distribution on the one hand, and the freedom of contract which allows parties to grant and take security on the other, by framing the issue thus:

Is the pari passu principle so strong that the burden of proving efficiency rests upon those who support secured credit, or is freedom of contract paramount so that the burden falls upon those who oppose security?192

Even without invoking freedom of contract,193 here (it is submitted) is the answer. The first premise of those attacking the priority accorded to secured claims—that unequal treatment of claims is anomalous, somehow a deviation from the ‘strong’ ‘equality’ norm—is quite false. If anything, it is the pari passu principle which constitutes an isolated enclave of ‘equality’ in a (formally) unequal insolvency world. In that real world, its status—considered as a rule governing distribution of assets—hovers somewhere between falsehood and tautology. So with respect, assertions that this principle is all-pervasive in the liquidation regime, that it underlies some of the best-known adjustment provisions of that regime, or that it provides the only alternative to an undesirable free-for-all, all stand rebutted as based on a fallacy. They must all be abandoned. So must the argument that the pari passu principle is necessary to ensure fairness in liquidation.

It is submitted that it is the critics of differing priorities for different types of claim, including those attacking the full priority of secured claims, who must now be on the defensive, at least on these grounds. The general rule in insolvency law, its deeply-embedded norm, seems to be that the assets available in insolvent estates are to be distributed ‘unequally’, unless attempting to do so would be wasteful because pointless. It might be that the different priorities afforded to different types of claimant are sometimes arbitrary. It might be that this area of the law could do with extensive rethinking and rationalization. Even then, it would not follow that what should replace the current system is one which crudely ‘equalizes’ all creditors in their debtor’s insolvency. Formal equality of that sort is not the natural alternative. It will not win by default. Not only is it rare and unnecessary in the real world, it is also useless as an ideal. So it must be argued for as much as any other system of priorities—whether the one we now have, or any proposed as a replacement—and it would be at least as contentious as any of them. Those arguing for (a more) ‘equal’ treatment of all claims must therefore bear the heavy burden of showing why moves towards formal equality are desirable.


BY 

Rizwaan Jameel Mokal

Comments